Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item:
http://hdl.handle.net/1893/28876
Full metadata record
DC Field | Value | Language |
---|---|---|
dc.contributor.author | Mandrigin, Alisa | en_UK |
dc.date.accessioned | 2019-03-02T01:02:53Z | - |
dc.date.available | 2019-03-02T01:02:53Z | - |
dc.date.issued | 2021-03 | en_UK |
dc.identifier.uri | http://hdl.handle.net/1893/28876 | - |
dc.description.abstract | In bodily awareness body parts are felt to occupy locations relative to the rest of the body. Bodily sensations are felt to be, in Brian O’Shaughnessy’s terms ‘in-a-certain-body-part-at-a-position-in-body-relative-physical-space’. In this paper I put forward a dispositional account of the structure of the spatial content of bodily awareness, which takes inspiration from Gareth Evans’s account of egocentric spatial content presented in The Varieties of Reference (1982). On the Dispositional View, bodily awareness experiences have spatial content in virtue of a set of connections having been established between somatosensory and proprioceptive inputs on the one hand, and motor outputs on the other hand. This kind of account, according to which spatial content depends constitutively on bodily action, has been challenged by a set of neurological cases and behavioural studies on healthy subjects. The evidence has been used to motivate a functional distinction between two kinds of body representation: representations for perception and representations for action. I review and assess some of the main sources of evidence for this distinction, arguing that the evidence presents a challenge to the dispositional view only if we accept the unjustified assumption that differences in task performance can only be explained in terms of a difference in representation. I close by proposing, and offering some empirical support for, an alternative explanation of the empirical results. The availability of the alternative explanation means that further work is needed to establish whether or not there is any challenge to the Dispositional View. | en_UK |
dc.language.iso | en | en_UK |
dc.publisher | BMC | en_UK |
dc.relation | Mandrigin A (2021) The where of bodily awareness. Synthese, 198 (3), pp. 1887-1903. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02171-3 | en_UK |
dc.rights | © The Author(s) 2019 This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. | en_UK |
dc.rights.uri | http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ | en_UK |
dc.subject | Bodily awareness | en_UK |
dc.subject | Spatial content | en_UK |
dc.subject | Proprioception | en_UK |
dc.subject | Touch | en_UK |
dc.subject | Body representation | en_UK |
dc.subject | Perception | en_UK |
dc.title | The where of bodily awareness | en_UK |
dc.type | Journal Article | en_UK |
dc.identifier.doi | 10.1007/s11229-019-02171-3 | en_UK |
dc.citation.jtitle | Synthese | en_UK |
dc.citation.issn | 1573-0964 | en_UK |
dc.citation.issn | 0039-7857 | en_UK |
dc.citation.volume | 198 | en_UK |
dc.citation.issue | 3 | en_UK |
dc.citation.spage | 1887 | en_UK |
dc.citation.epage | 1903 | en_UK |
dc.citation.publicationstatus | Published | en_UK |
dc.citation.peerreviewed | Refereed | en_UK |
dc.type.status | VoR - Version of Record | en_UK |
dc.contributor.funder | John Templeton Foundation | en_UK |
dc.contributor.funder | Arts and Humanities Research Council | en_UK |
dc.author.email | alisa.mandrigin@stir.ac.uk | en_UK |
dc.citation.date | 08/04/2019 | en_UK |
dc.contributor.affiliation | Psychology | en_UK |
dc.identifier.isi | WOS:000632459900002 | en_UK |
dc.identifier.wtid | 1236477 | en_UK |
dc.contributor.orcid | 0000-0002-3635-9897 | en_UK |
dc.date.accepted | 2019-02-14 | en_UK |
dcterms.dateAccepted | 2019-02-14 | en_UK |
dc.date.filedepositdate | 2019-03-01 | en_UK |
dc.subject.tag | Philosophy of Mind and Action | en_UK |
dc.subject.tag | Mind and Knowledge | en_UK |
rioxxterms.apc | not required | en_UK |
rioxxterms.type | Journal Article/Review | en_UK |
rioxxterms.version | VoR | en_UK |
local.rioxx.author | Mandrigin, Alisa|0000-0002-3635-9897 | en_UK |
local.rioxx.project | Project ID unknown|John Templeton Foundation|http://dx.doi.org/10.13039/100000925 | en_UK |
local.rioxx.project | Project ID unknown|Arts and Humanities Research Council|http://dx.doi.org/10.13039/501100000267 | en_UK |
local.rioxx.freetoreaddate | 2019-04-08 | en_UK |
local.rioxx.licence | http://www.rioxx.net/licenses/under-embargo-all-rights-reserved||2019-04-08 | en_UK |
local.rioxx.licence | http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/|2019-04-08| | en_UK |
local.rioxx.filename | Mandrigin2021_Article_TheWhereOfBodilyAwareness.pdf | en_UK |
local.rioxx.filecount | 1 | en_UK |
local.rioxx.source | 1573-0964 | en_UK |
Appears in Collections: | Psychology Journal Articles |
Files in This Item:
File | Description | Size | Format | |
---|---|---|---|---|
Mandrigin2021_Article_TheWhereOfBodilyAwareness.pdf | Fulltext - Published Version | 268.87 kB | Adobe PDF | View/Open |
This item is protected by original copyright |
A file in this item is licensed under a Creative Commons License
Items in the Repository are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise indicated.
The metadata of the records in the Repository are available under the CC0 public domain dedication: No Rights Reserved https://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/
If you believe that any material held in STORRE infringes copyright, please contact library@stir.ac.uk providing details and we will remove the Work from public display in STORRE and investigate your claim.